Untangling Electoral Reform
'Who rules?' is a central question for a mature society. Answering it requires a clear understanding of the complexity inherent in it.
In my last post, I suggested that the foundations of democratic accountability lie more in the public’s ability to dismiss their leaders, than in the ability to choose them. But how we choose them is, of course, also very important.
In democratic societies where elections four or five years apart are the only opportunity for the public to dismiss their government or their representatives, the importance of the electoral process is hugely magnified. It’s not surprising , therefore, that campaigners seeking to improve government make electoral reform their top priority.
Sometimes, alas, their only priority.
For those of us who take a broader view, a major stumbling-block is the fact that, although no single change is likely to be truly transformative on its own, most people assume that constitutional reform can only happen one step at a time. As a result, much of the thinking about it looks at each problem in isolation — and the solutions people come up with tend to be designed to fit in with the system in its current form.
In Britain, proportional representation (PR) seems to have become the clear favourite, among activists, to replace the current first-past-the-post system — and it’s a good example of this piecemeal approach to reform.
It would certainly be easy to integrate PR into our current system but would it in fact have a place in a coherent constitution? Are political parties so intrinsically necessary to effective democracy that their role should be entrenched? And, if efforts to introduce PR do succeed, will they take us closer to a genuinely healthy system – or could they be at best a distraction and at worst a hindrance?
Advocates of PR generally take it for granted that political parties are essential. As a result, they fail to recognise that the dominant role parties play in our current system could be the result of deeper constitutional flaws.
Before we can properly understand how other aspects of the constitution might affect the outcome of elections, however, we need to be clear about what dilemmas the electoral framework itself confronts us with. For this, we need to distinguish between electoral systems and the individual elements that constitute them. Specifically: the voting process (which is the main focus of this article) and the framework of representation (which will be the focus of a future article).
Electoral systems unpicked
The marks that voters are allowed to put on ballot papers, and the rules governing how votes should be counted (the voting process) are distinct from questions such as how many representatives a constituency elects, what their role is, and who is eligible to be elected (the framework of representation).
Specific combinations of voting process and framework of representation (constituting electoral systems) are often compared to each other in terms of the outcomes they produce. But simple comparisons of electoral systems make it difficult to appreciate the underlying issues.
As I see it, there are two distinct aspects to electoral reform:
an essentially technical question of what voting process would best serve the purpose for which elections are held; and
a more clearly political question of what framework of representation should be used.
These questions are wholly independent of each other – single-option voting (in which voters simply put a cross by a single candidate’s name) or preferential voting (which allows voters to rank candidates) can both be used with either single-member or multi-member constituencies. The merits and flaws of different solutions can only be properly appreciated when the questions are examined separately. Unfortunately, debate on electoral reform has generally focused on electoral systems, obscuring the fact that these distinct questions really need to be answered in isolation.
For example, the debate in the UK has mostly centred on the relative merits of the Alternative Vote system (AV, known as ranked voting or preferential voting in some countries) and the Single Transferable Vote system (STV) and tends to focus on the outcomes they produce. But this framing of the debate ignores the fact that the only change involved in AV is also present in STV; both depend on a relatively simple reform (replacing single-option voting with preferential voting) but STV involves a couple of additional reforms whose advantages and disadvantages are very much harder to weigh up (switching from single-member to multi-member constituencies, and adding a refinement to the vote counting process). From the perspective of what reforms are necessary, therefore, these cannot be regarded as competing options; any decision to adopt STV implies acceptance of the principle underlying AV.
Framing the debate
How we frame the debate has significant ramifications, both in terms of how easily reforms can be understood by the wider public and in terms of what lines of argument might prove most effective.
This was almost certainly a factor in the public’s lack of engagement with the UK’s referendum in 2011. That ballot asked the public ‘At present, the UK uses the “first past the post” system to elect MPs to the House of Commons. Should the “alternative vote” system be used instead?’. Well, in my experience, plenty of people who are deeply engaged with politics don’t really know what the “alternative vote” system entails, so how much meaning would that question have had for people who aren’t politically engaged?
Most of the public, as far as I can see, just want the politicians to get on with running the country honestly and fairly – do we really expect them to inform themselves about the intricacies of different voting systems? 58% of the electorate didn’t vote in that referendum — how many of them simply didn’t engage with the issue because they didn’t know what the question meant, and felt it was a technical issue that wasn’t their business?
Suppose the question had been ‘At present, to elect MPs to the House of Commons, UK voters may only mark ballot papers with a single “X” against their preferred candidate. Should they be allowed to use numbers instead to indicate all their preferred candidates in order?’. With no special knowledge needed, the public would have found it much easier to engage with the issue and some of the spurious objections (like the claim that AV means people who support unpopular candidates get more votes than people who support popular ones) would have been much less likely to take root.
Many people would still have thought that it wasn’t their business, though — quite reasonably, to my mind. Why was it that the public were expected to decide on a technical question like that? Because, by framing the debate in terms of competing electoral systems, reformers had made it easy for their opponents to claim it was such a major constitutional change that it must be explicitly sanctioned by the electorate.
If we frame it, instead, as an essentially technical question – what voting process would best serve the purpose for which elections are held? – we can confront opponents with the weakness of their own case. Supporters of single-option voting justify it with the argument that it usually provides strong government, whereas other systems generally lead to coalitions that are weak and indecisive and unable to govern effectively. Reformers all too often fall into the trap of disputing that argument on its own terms, pointing to examples where first-past-the-post has led to hung parliaments or preferential voting has produced decisive governments. By doing that, they implicitly accept that providing strong government is a primary purpose of holding an election.
A more productive response would be to challenge opponents of reform to prove their argument’s relevance. Imagine putting this question to the public in a referendum: ‘Do you believe the essential purpose of holding ballots to elect MPs to the House of Commons is a) to put into power a strong government who will be able to implement bold policies, or b) to allow the electorate to express its will in regard to how the country is run?’. Most people, I suspect, will regard such a question as absurd and take it for granted that the electorate would overwhelmingly choose the second answer.
If we can establish clearly what the essential purpose of elections is, the question of what voting process would best serve that purpose no longer needs to be be regarded as political. And that brings us to another question which opens up a new avenue for pursuing reform.
Conflict of interests
Is it proper for Members of Parliament to decide the details of how they themselves are elected? It is, after all, a well-established principle that people in positions of power should delegate decisions to independent agents when a conflict of interests compromises their own ability to decide impartially. Is there not a clear conflict of interest here between MPs’ loyalty to their party and their duty to represent all their constituents?
Electoral reform has to be a high priority for anyone who wants to see a healthy system of government. But the current debate, with its focus on how well parties’ vote share is reflected in their share of seats, naturally leads MPs to consider what is in their own party’s best interests. Should we not re-frame the debate to make it easier for them to consider what integrity demands?
Rather than campaigning for Parliament to endorse some specific electoral system, reformers would do better to urge MPs to step aside from the issue. Let Parliament simply clarify the purpose for which elections are held and instruct some independent body, such as the Electoral Commission, to determine the technical details of how votes should be made and counted.
Conclusion
Once the question of the voting process is dealt with, we might find it becomes much easier to resolve the thornier problem of ensuring that each party’s presence in Parliament truly reflects its support among the public.
However, what the best form of representation would be, in a well-constituted society, also depends on a number of other questions: in particular, how abstentions and protest votes are dealt with; the relationships between different functions and branches of government; and the distribution of sovereignty.
I’ll be looking at some of those questions in more depth in future posts, and will subsequently explore how we might pursue reform if Members of Parliament wilfully ignore the conflict of interest and insist on their own right to keep a system which is so obviously unsatisfactory.
Hi Malcolm,
I noticed that in your welcome letter you refer to your 'narrow focus' - jurisprudence, and more specifically UK. But while systems as well as national proclivities change from one country to another, and therefore require specific and tailored solutions and changes, it seems to me that much of what you write about on T'reasonable Man is more universal - for instance the idea of involving juries in removing people from power, which I guess could in principle be done anywhere. This seems to me important - there is a hunger for 'new ways of doing things' all over the world now (reflecting that the time for change has come, globally - or to say it another way, the old ways of doing things are 'past their sell-by date, and are causing a lot of problems). Seems to me there are a lot more people saying 'we need new ways of doing things' than there are people offering serious thoughts on what those new ways are. That's part of what my World in Transition is about - as you know with a generally 'three-fold' perspective. But I think the more universal elements of T'Reasonable Man have much to offer to that debate too, beyond the UK.
Probalby some of your thinking will be very compatible with my three-fold perspective and perhaps some won't. But as you said in your 'Edge of Reason', we don't have to stay in our silos - goes for me too! Any serious new view for the future has to be worked out through the confluence of many ideas!
This is a reasonable take.
But I question why we "need" representatives at all. The signal from the noise, the "wisdom of the crowd" emerges from large numbers of people with diverse viewpoints. So, in that sense, we should be striving to bypass representatives and go straight to direct democracy.
Now, it's not feasible to bring everyone into Parliament, but we could use sortition to select thousands of individuals at random. Much cheaper and cleaner than elections, gathering diverse viewpoints from a broad range of people.